The State and the Kingdom of God

 Introduction

In international relations, three theories provide contrasting analyses and perspectives on governance in general.  This essay will introduce each theory, discuss it further in terms of governance, and then conclude with some contrasting thoughts about the Kingdom of God.  To some readers' consternation, I will equate the Kingdom of God with the Church on the grounds that Christ's reign as Lord is through His 'body', the Church, 'the fullness of him who fills all in all' (Ephesians 1.22-23).  The essay is intended as a discussion of the relationship of Church and State.  The argument is that some forms of government are more amenable to the Church, but the Church, insofar as it represents the Kingdom of God on earth, is an alternative community to government that does not replace government but is constructively critical of it.

Realism

Realism has a variety of forms, but its key tenets are, according to Tim Dunne and Brian Schmidt, statism, survival, and self-help.[1]  While political theorists may prefer definitions and distinctions in international relations theory to be expressed in post-World War I developments, Dunne and Schmidt understand classical realism to originate in ancient Greece, as in Thucydides’ rendition of negotiations between the powerful Athenians and the weaker Melians (History of the Peloponnesian War 5.84ff).  Whereas the Melians attempt to appeal to the ideal of justice, the Athenians respond with straight-forward realism: they are the stronger and, as such, will do what they please and the Melians will be forced into submission.  The Melians appeal to fair play and just dealings, but the Athenians respond that the fight is not fair: the question is whether the Melians want to save their lives in the face of the more powerful force or not.  The Melians then suggest that the gods may look with favour upon them despite their inferior strength.  To this argument, the Athenians offer a realistic response, the safe rule in life that one should stand up to equals, show deference to superiors, and treat inferiors with moderation.  The Melians look to something outside the situation—outside the relationship between the two states: justice, the gods, and also the hope they place in having an ally, the Spartans.  The Athenian position demonstrates a unifying theme for realism: outside state relationships there is nothing to which one might appeal (outside states, there is in the international sphere only anarchy).  If so, the state does not exist because of some external authority but because of its own, internal power.  Thus, survival depends on a state’s looking to its own needs and defenses.  This, then, points realists to the need for self-help.  States should not rely on others for their own defense or thriving.  They should not rely on international institutions or allies, and they should not outsource their key industries to other nations or be overly dependent on others for their resources.

A key realist in the Enlightenment era was Thomas Hobbes.  Hobbes, writing in England during the Civil War, found the state of nature to be chaotic and dangerous.  Nature endowed individuals with an equality of body and mind as well as an equality of hope in attainment of our goals, but one could not locate politics in any natural bonds that draw humans into community (Leviathan, 13.60-61).  Indeed, this ‘equality of hope’ to attain our goals leads human beings to formulate ways and means to take from others what they want for themselves.  To protect against this, individuals band together, forming social contracts that they might provide mutual protection against aggressors.  Hobbes says that there are, in the nature of man, three principal causes of quarreling: competition, diffidence, and glory.  ‘The first, maketh man invade for Gain; the second, for Safety [the need for defense], and the third, for Reputation’ (13.62).[2]

Realism need not be considered an a-moral theory of international relations.  Realism is not synonymous with ‘might is right’, although that is the tenor of the Athenian argument with the Melians.  Hans J. Morgenthau argued with ‘Classical Realism’ that power is the medium for a state’s actions—it is what will permit them to (or obstruct them from) doing whatever they wish to do.[3]  This perspective was advanced with ‘Structural Realism’ (or ‘Neorealism’) in the Cold War period by Kenneth Waltz, when the bipolar balance of power between the superpowers of the United States and the Soviet Union dominated international politics.[4]  Waltz argued that states were ultimately concerned with security, not simply power, which was the means to security.  Neoclassical realism since the end of the Cold War introduces the notion that the perceptions of leaders and internal, domestic politics also influence international politics.

The strength of realism is, simply, that it is realistic.  This comes across already in the response of the Athenians to the Milenians.  Ideals and theory aside, facts are facts, and the fact of the matter is that power wins.  The challenge for realists is not in the facts but in distinguishing the possession and use of power from ethics rather than intertwining them: might does not make right even if it does describe how international relations work.  Where, then, is a moral authority to be located if not in power?  For this, we turn to suggestions in a second theory: liberalism.

Liberalism

Liberalism, in the sense of international relations, arises after the religious wars of Europe in the period of the Enlightenment.  The term ‘liberalism’ is confusingly fluid and broad.  Helen Pluckrose and James Lindsay say that the

main tenets of liberalism are political democracy, limitations on the power of government, the development of universal human rights, legal equality for all adult citizens, freedom of expression, respect for the value of viewpoint diversity and honest debate, respect for evidence and reason, the separation of church and state, and freedom of religion.[5]

Discussion here, however, is focused on liberalism as a theory in international relations.  Three thinkers might be considered from the Enlightenment period of the 1700s in discussing this view: John Locke (1632-1704), Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), and Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832).  The tenets of liberalism might, however, be contrasted with realism, already discussed.

John Locke argued (Two Treatises 2) that natural law was an important reality that could and should be taken into consideration even when individual states may not have developed certain laws to punish wrongful behaviour.  Roman law was founded on the view that there were three types of law: the law of nature, the law of nations (international law), and the laws of specific peoples.  In Locke’s view, nations may agree that a law of nature has been broken and punish persons whether or not their countries had prescribed laws to do with some specific act.  Furthermore, punishment may be applied internationally where natural law has been broken, such as in the case of war crimes.  Locke advocated that natural law protected life, liberty, and property (amended to ‘the pursuit of happiness’ in the American Declaration of Independence).  Locke’s arguments highlight key contentions for liberalism: the notion that there is more than just the self-interest of individual states seeking their own ends; the notion of natural law; and the articulation of natural law in terms of universal truths.  These are key tenets of liberalism.  We might add one additional point from Locke that he held to be essential: the positive laws of a state are those that are based in natural law (Two Treatises 2.12).  If so, then the laws of a particular nation might be judged in light of the higher law of nature and—anticipating the discussion of constructivism—the laws of a nation are not to be established on the mere majority agreement of its citizenry.  Thus,

If the rule of law is ignored, if the representatives of the people are prevented from assembling, if the mechanisms of election are altered without popular consent, or if the people are handed over to a foreign power, then they can take back their original authority and overthrow the government (2.212–17).[6]

Natural law, then, stood over both domestic and international law and is a fundamental concept for liberalism’s holding the power of a state or of states to account.

Kant’s argument was that liberal states tended toward peace rather than war.  Three things, he argued, are necessary to foster peace.  First, a republican government—one requiring the consent of the citizens—would more likely deter countries from war than a monarchical government would.  Second, a league or ‘pacific federation’ with its own constitution would foster peace among the participant nations.  Third, Kant encourages a ‘cosmopolitan right’ that has to do with human good (cf. ‘human rights’).  One can easily see the outline of the later League of Nations and United Nations in the 20th century, the latter having a charter that describes various human rights.  Kant’s plan is not based on the independent rights of states but on the universalism of humanity across national boundaries.  The universalism of Kant, therefore, is key to his politics as it is to his ethics, in which the ‘categorical imperative’—a universal principle that what is right for one must be right because it is right for all—is fundamental.

Jeremy Bentham’s ethics is often contrasted with Kant’s in that he proposed, alternatively, the utilitarian principle for deciding moral actions.  This principle located ‘the good’ in the greatest good for the greatest number of people.  (Note that this definition still fails to define ‘the good’ and on what authority people have the right to determine it.)  As applied to international relations, Bentham, firstly, introduced the term ‘international’ to replace the Roman ‘law of nations’.  The latter term relied on custom and convention rather than agreement on law between nations.  Note that Bentham locates the law by which states might operate not in natural law, as did Locke, but in his equivalent for the law of nations. Secondly, he sought an agreement between nations that there is an equality of sovereigns.  This restricts a state’s justification of its use of power simply because it is the more powerful.  However, it does not locate the restriction in God’s authority over the nations.  Thirdly, he called for legislators and judges to seek among the family of nations the greatest happiness.[7]  While this utilitarian principle of the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people is popular to this day, it is notoriously slippery in application. 

All three of these arguments from Bentham are attempts to locate an authority outside the power of a particular state apart from God or theology and involve a trust in the goodness of humanity.  The same might be said of Kant’s proposals.  Only Locke appeals to divine authority, even if only in vague terms.  It is God as Creator and Sustainer of our world rather than God as the revealer of moral law (as in the Mosaic Law) who holds an authority above the rights of nations in their use of power.  We might say that Kant and Bentham have bought the serpent’s argument with Eve in the Garden of Eden: men and women may become like God in their exercise of reason to know right and wrong.  Deists like Locke, however, contended that, just as nations require an external authority over the use of their power, so also humans need an external authority of their reasoning power as to what is right and wrong.

Constructivism

Upon the impending demise of the Soviet Union and the end of the Cold War and in an age of postmodernity, Nicholas Onuf proposed in 1989 that international relations are constructed.[8]  Another key proponent of constructivism is Alexander Wendt, whose article, ‘Anarchy is What States Make of It: the Social Construction of Power Politics,’ appeared in 1992.[9]  He writes, ‘identities and interests [not the ‘self-help’ interest of realism] of states are socially constructed [not ‘exogenously given’, as in neoliberal theories, but ‘endogenous’] by knowledgeable practice.’[10]  He redefines ‘self-help’ as a process whereby states develop their self-interests rather than respond to the anarchic forces of power-politics in international relations.  Also, Wendt notes that both realism and liberalism are rationalist in their seeking to change behaviour through reasoning rather than, as constructivism, seeking to change actual identity and interests.  They assume that ‘states are the dominant actors in the system.’[11]

This new theory holds that human association is, first, not primarily grounded in material forces but in shared ideas and, second, these shared ideas help construct the identities and interest of the actors in international relations.  Perceptions, social norms, actions, and interactions shape politics.  As Wendt says, ‘A fundamental principle of constructivist social theory is that people act towards objects, including other actors, on the basis of meanings that the object have for them.’[12]  If the object is perceived as an enemy rather than a friend, an individual or state will act differently.  Quoting Peter Berger, Wendt writes, “Identity, with its appropriate attachments of psychological reality, is always identity within a specific, socially constructed world.”[13]  Expanding on Berger’s and Luckman’s understanding of the interplay between individuals and society in the construction of the identity of both, they say,

Identity is a key element of subjective reality and, like all subjective reality, stands in dialectical relationship with society.  Identity is formed by social processes.  Once crystallized, it is maintained, modified, or even reshaped by social relations. The social processes involved in both the formation and maintenance of identity are determined by social structures.  Conversely, the identities produced by the interplay of organism, individual consciousness and social structure react upon the given social structure, maintaining it, modifying it, or even reshaping it.[14]

Along these lines, Wendt suggests that ‘an institution is a relatively stable set or “structure” of identities and interests.’[15]  So, ‘institutionalization is a process of internalizing new identities and interests, not something occurring outside them and affecting only behaviour.’  Given this, state relations are not merely about power and institutions.  A more dynamic and constructive view adds that they are also about expectations and understandings arising from the institutional identities and interests that participants in them form.  Thus, relations begin with agency (the agency of the body for individuals and the agency of the apparatus of governance for the state) and the desire to survive.[16]  States, like individuals, take their agencies and desire to survive into their encounters with others and produce identity and interests in the interactions and relationships that develop, whether friendly or hostile.[17]

Weaknesses in constructivism are likely not so much in their description of some aspects of relationships but in their failure to give an adequate account of identity and interests beyond agency and the desire to survive.  The description they offer is a sort of myth of origins that omits other key aspects of real relationships determined (not constructed) by history and religion in particular and of identity that includes some notion of morality—what is right objectively.  Islam, for example, makes no distinction between religion and the state.  Its identity is formed as an interpretation of Islamic Law, history, and goals to convert or dominate everyone else.  Its core identity is ‘submission’ in the sense of submission to Allah’s rule and therefore to Islamic rule living under that rule.  This view requires an understanding of relations that goes quite beyond agency and the desire to survive.  In the end, Thomas Hobbes’ realism that states form for survival against hostile forces (Leviathan) offers a better lens to interpret relationships with Islamic states.

The Kingdom of God

What lies behind constructivism’s failure in this regard is its denial of a moral order—the very thing that liberalism insisted on but increasingly did so only in terms of a European Deism and subsequent secularism rather than a Biblical worldview.  We might add here that African traditional religion also posited divinity behind and above interactions, but with so vague an understanding of this that it amounted to little beyond sacrifices (including human) to appease the spiritual forces. A Biblical perspective gives far more clarity and detail to divine rule and expresses what this means through the pages of Scripture.

Furthermore, constructivism has to deny any fundamentally evil principle in the world.  It may be true that institutions do not have to be the way they are but can be perceived and used according to human identities and intentions in relationships.  This view is fundamentally undermined, however, if there is an operative evil in the world whose agency is not amoral and whose desire to survive is a desire to survive as a force of lies, evil, and destruction.  If so, international relations are not limited to the self-help and survival of states (realism) or the self-making through agency and the desire to survive of states defining their identity and interests in relationships with others (constructivism).  They may be formed more fundamentally by powers beyond themselves, whether by God in His goodness or by demonic forces.  This was the view of the Greek and Roman world.  Jews and Christians added to this an historical perspective, or a narrative perspective with a beginning, middle, and end to the story.  What is happening now is part of a larger narrative of God’s salvation history.

One question the early Church asked was whether government was a demonic force.  It asked this for very good reason: its regular encounter with government was often negative.  The New Testament offers different answers to the question, since some governmental authority is God-ordained but government can and often does abuse its authority.  One thing was certain: government was not the Kingdom of God.  Several texts need to be considered to answer this question and to come to something like an early Church understanding of Church and State.

The first relationship between Church and State is Jesus’ famous distinction between things religious and things to do with the State: ‘render to Caesar the things that are Caesar’s, and to God the things that are God’s’ (Mark 12.17, ESV).  At one level, this statement makes room to pay required taxes and, by extension, to abide by the State’s laws.  At another level, this relativizes the State’s authority, declaring that it does not have authority in matters of Christian religion.  As Peter famously said to the high priest and the Jewish Council, ‘We must obey God rather than any human authority’ (Acts 5.29).  This Council held authority over religious and Jewish civil affairs in Jerusalem.  Peter’s response to the Council states more than the separation of Church and State.  He first contrasts God’s Law with any human authority, whether in the religious institution or in the State.  He second insists that God’s Law is above human authorities.

The second type of relationship between Church and State is found in Romans 13.1-8.  Paul affirms that the State has its purpose and authority from God.  He writes,

Romans 13.1-4 Let every person be subject to the governing authorities; for there is no authority except from God, and those authorities that exist have been instituted by God….  For rulers are not a terror to good conduct, but to bad.  Do you wish to have no fear of the authority?  Then do what is good, and you will receive its approval; for it is God’s servant for your good.  But if you do what is wrong, you should be afraid, for the authority does not bear the sword in vain!  It is the servant of God to execute wrath on the wrongdoer.

In context, this passage follows Paul’s call on believers not to take revenge on their enemies but to do good to them, leaving vengeance to God (Romans 12.17-21, quoting Proverbs 25.21-22).  This perspective brings out a different nuance from the first.  The separation here is not so absolute, not so black and white.  God’s authority can work through human authorities; God can delegate His authority, as it were.  This understanding of government authority is that it brings order in an otherwise chaotic and sinful world.  We see God doing this already in creation in Genesis 1.1-2.3. The divine function of ruling is to bring order.  Similarly, 2 Thessalonians pictures the current situation in the world in terms of the restraint of lawlessness and rebellion—by which we should understand opposition to God’s Law.  The passages speaks of a future time when this restraint will be removed and the man of lawlessness revealed.  On this understanding, God sets in place what is needed, such as government, to restrain lawlessness—to hold back the chaos monster, as it were.  We might contrast a contemporary view of government that sees the State as the guarantor of freedom rather than the authority to restrain lawlessness.  The restraint of lawlessness is not a blanket approval of State authority, though.  ‘Lawlessness’ is understood religiously—God’s Law.  The State itself can be criticized if it sets its power in motion not to restrain but to promote what is opposed to God’s Law.  Thus, government stands under God.

The third, slightly different perspective is in 1 Timothy 2.1-8.  Paul affirms the traditional Jewish perspective that believers should pray for those in powerful and authoritative positions.  This is, however, not because they support the authorities but because prayer can lead to God’s purpose being worked through people in positions of authority.  In particular, the prayer is directed to God’s mission that all might be saved and come to a knowledge of the truth (v. 4). 

The fourth perspective comprises all the book of Revelation.  In Revelation, the overly powerful State usurps divine authority and persecutes the Church.  The problem is not just that people do bad things, it is that the power of the State takes on an absolute authority of its own.  This is the situation that elicits apocalyptic literature like Daniel and Revelation.  These four perspectives are, to be sure, compatible.  They bring out different aspects of the relationship between Church and State.

There is a difference between ‘big government’ and government that wrestles away power from the people, although the two certainly go together.  We have seen in recent years a shift from concern about big government to a government of (over) rather than by the people.  A big government, it is well-argued, is a government that is at best clumsy for its bureaucracy.  It is often inefficient (or dangerously efficient in some things), expensive, ‘stupid’ for its lack of nuance, inattentive to local concerns, process-driven, legalistic, and operated by unelected officials who can and do establish a deep state.

The first half of the twentieth century saw fundamental disagreement over ideologies: communist, fascist, democratic (and still, to some extent, monarchic).  Such battles will surely reappear, but the current fracturing of civil society is occurring within the democratic option.  Democracy was long seen as the antidote to tyranny.  What has developed, however, is a democratic tyranny. This tyranny functions in two ways: (1) as the overreaching power of a democratically elected government; (2) as an oppression of the minority by the majority.  The American founding fathers anticipated this when instituting a democratic government, which is why they instituted an electoral college, a representational legislature in the Senate, a separation of powers, and various checks and balances.  This was the main concern in James Madison’s Federalist Paper No. 10, in which he contends that a republican form of government rather than pure democracy can safeguard against majority domination or unrepresented minorities.  The problem is no longer ‘big government’; it is now a powerful government that restricts individual freedoms.  The system of government was meant to protect citizens not only from the tyranny of the majority but also from the majority voting in a different system that would shut out minority voices and concerns.  Christians ought always to understand their presence in society is as a minority voice, and they should, therefore, be deeply concerned with governments that lack protection of and freedom for its minority groups.

Another dimension to Christian thought about government is the existence not of an alternative world government but of an alternative people, the Church.  The Church is the institutional alternative to government, but it can exist alongside of and independently from government because it is a different order altogether.  One of the fatal flaws of much Christian thinking about social justice is its thinking of what this means for government and society rather than, or more than, of what it means for the Church.  The Church is God’s people embodying His reign on the earth.  Christ Jesus reigns now over the Church as He will over everything in the future; the Church is Christ’s body in the present world, the present fullness of Him is filling all things with the presence of God.  What this meant for the early Christians is that their focus in social justice was in who they were—their identity and interests, which were formed in Christ and were, therefore, Christ’s identity and interests.  Being Christ in the world, the Church could illuminate the world with the light of God’s rule.

This answers the alternative theories considered here in international relations.  It does not answer them in the sense that the Kingdom of God is the right theory where these other theories are wrong because the Church is not a real alternative to government in the sense of intending to overthrow or replace it.  The Church gives up necessary actions in this present world that government performs.  Thus, the Church represents to government what God’s reign involves without itself becoming a government.  As Paul points out in Romans 12.17-13.7, the Church gives up the sword of retribution and punishment in pursuit of justice, but God empowers government to deliver order and justice in a sinful world.  This is no outright endorsement of any actual government, all of which are faulty.  It removes the sword from the Church.

Paul also offers a view of government in terms of God’s hand holding back the apocalyptic forces of lawlessness in 2 Thessalonians 2.26-28:

26 And you know what is restraining him now so that he may be revealed in his time.  27 For the mystery of lawlessness mis already at work. Only he who now restrains it will do so until he is out of the way.  28 And then the lawless one will be revealed, whom the Lord Jesus will kill with the breath of his mouth and bring to nothing by the appearance of his coming (ESV).

A secular version of this would simply speak of ‘pariah states’ or ‘predator states’ that come and go, without a notion of this culminating in a final unleashing of evil.  There are states that are evil for impersonal, systemic reasons, but there are also states that are evil for the intentional, personal reasons of their rulers and those in authority.  The immense evil of the state could be equated with evil leaders and their henchmen.  If any passage comes close to a view of international relations like that of Thomas Hobbes, it is 2 Thessalonians 2, which simply reflects a deeply held perspective in apocalyptic Judaism.  1 Enoch 91.5-7 speaks of a state of violence that will intensify on the earth and then references a great plague on the earth, oppression, everything being uprooted, warfare, and the increase of sin, blasphemy, injustice, crime, iniquity, uncleanliness (cf. Jubilees 23.14-25; 2 Baruch 27).  In regard to 2 Thessalonians 2’s ‘man of lawlessness,’ Eugene Boring notes that the Roman general, Pompey, who ‘evoked apostasy, scattered the covenant people, and even entered the holy of holies,’ was called the ‘Lawless One.’[18]  F. F. Bruce suggested that the image of the man of lawlessness is built on Old Testament and Jewish notions of a wicked leader.  The most interesting of his suggestions is Isaiah 14.12-15.  The King of Babylon is said to boast that he will rise above the clouds to make himself like the Most High, but he will be brought down to Sheol.[19]  Greg Beale suggests, rather, that the man of lawlessness is based on Daniel 11.29-34,[20] which speaks of the return of Antiochus IV Epiphanes to attack Egypt but then turn to attack ‘the holy covenant’.  He will profane the temple and fortress, remove the regular burnt sacrifice, and set up the abomination that makes desolate (vv. 30-31).  He will seduce people to violate the covenant, while some would stand firm even though they will ‘stumble by sword and flame, by captivity and plunder’ (v. 33).  God’s people will be ‘refined, purified, and made white’ with the stumbling of some (v. 35).

Conclusion

Some governmental forms are better than others, and some are more amenable to the Church than others.  Yet form is only one aspect of a larger discussion of Church and State.  Even better forms of government can be problematic.  The Church exists as a community with convictions, ethics, and activities that can support or challenge governments.  It is not itself a government.  It is high functioning within its own community and can be exemplary to the State as to what it ought to do.  The Church’s voice and nature of community ought to be a prophetic voice to the State.  Yet the State is not the Church, and there are things that the Church does that the State ought not to try to do (enforce religion, e.g.).  One of the matters distinguishing Church and State is that of power.  The Church—when it truly is the Church and not some misrepresentation of it—understands power through the cross of Jesus Christ.  It rejects the means of power of the State either by seeing it as a legitimate form of justice in a sinful world, with qualifications, or as an abusive aggression that needs to be challenged, just as the prophets of old would challenge the governments of Israel for their religious and social abuses.

The Church shares perspectives with realism, liberalism, and constructivism in international relations theory while remaining distinct—and critical—of each.  With realism, it acknowledges that the fall of humanity into sin is pervasive.  Government is necessary to hold back the powers of evil and chaos.  Self-preservation is legitimate, as are freedom and flourishing (life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness).  Yet the Church agrees with liberalism in the sense that something does stand above the State that is universal and moral.  The classic Biblical text supporting this view is Psalm 2.  Enlightenment liberalism, however, pushes God further and further from identifying Him as what stands over the State, over the king, over government, over international relations, and over the morality of cultures.  The Church proclaims that there is One God over all and Jesus as Lord.  Finally, with constructivism, the Church recognizes that the current state of politics—before the return of Jesus to judge all people and nations—is not universal.  Cultures create identities, with their norms and laws.  This is one way of stating that the Church is not a State but a distinct community among other communities.  It operates internationally as an alternative community within and across state boundaries with a mission to the world that determines its own identities and expresses its own interests in accordance with its identity—an identity established by Holy Scripture, God’s authoritative Word, and exemplified, for better or for worse, in the Church.

[1] Tim Dunne and Brian C. Schmidt, ‘Chapter 8: Realism,’ in The Globalization of World Politics: An Introduction to International Relations, 8th ed., ed. John Baylis, Steve Smith, Patricia Owens (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 2020), pp. 130-144.

[2] Hobbes, Leviathan, rev. student edition, ed. Richard Tuck (Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought; Cambridge: Cambridge Univ., 1991).

[3] See Ibid., pp. 136-137.  Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 4th ed. (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1948).

[4] Kenneth Waltz, Theory of International Politics (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1979).

[5] Helen Pluckrose and James Lindsay, Cynical Theories: How Activist Scholarship Made Everything about Race, Gender, and Identity—and Why This Harms Everything (Durham, NC: Pitchstone Pub., 2020).

[6] ‘Locke’s Political Philosophy,’ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (rev. 2020); online https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/locke-political/#:~:text=Locke%20describes%20international%20relations%20as,in%20the%20state%20of%20nature.. See section 6.

[7] Tim Dunne, ‘Liberal Internationalism,’ in The Globalization of World Politics, pp. 103-114.  See p. 105.

[8] Nicholas Onuf, World of our Making (Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press, 1989).

[9] Alexander Wendt, ‘Anarchy is What States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics,’ International Organization, Vol. 46, No. 2. (Spring, 1992), pp. 391-425. 

[10] Ibid.  The quotation is from the abstract of the article.

[11] Ibid., p. 392.

[12] Ibid., p. 396-397.

[13] Ibid., p. 397-398.  See Peter Berger, ‘Identity as a Problem in the Sociology of Knowledge,’ European Journal of Sociology 7.1 (1966), pp. 32-40.  The connection of constructivism to Peter Berger helps readers to see the larger picture: constructivism is an application of a sociology of knowledge that involves a variety of thinkers such as Berger and Michel Foucault.  See Reiner Keller, ‘The Sociology of Knowledge Approach to Discourse (SKAD),’ Human Studies 34.1 (Spring, 2011), pp. 43-65.

[14] Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann, The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge (London: Allen Lane, 1966),  p. 194.

[15] Wendt, p. 399.

[16] Ibid., p. 402.

[17] Wendt offers a systemic diagramme to illustrate the interactions.  Ibid., p. 406.

[18] He references (Psalms of Solomon 17.11-22; Josephus, Antiquities of the Jews 14.71-72; Jewish Wars 1.152-153).  See M. Eugene Boring, I and II Thessalonians: A Commentary (Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press), p. 273.

[19] F. F. Bruce, 1 and 2 Thessalonians, Word Biblical Commentary, Vo. 45, rev. ed. (Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan Academic, 2017).

[20] G. K. Beale, 1 and 2 Thessalonians (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity, 2010), p. 206.

No comments:

The Second Week of Advent: Preparing for the peace of God

[An Advent Homily] The second Sunday in Advent carries the theme, ‘preparation for the peace of God’.   That peace comes with the birth of C...

Popular Posts