The Foetus, Culture, and Law: Some Brief Reflections on Egypt, Greece, Rome, and the West Today

 What view did ancient Egypt take on the status of the foetus, and what reasoning was given?  Unlike several other ancient societies in the Ancient Near East, we do not have surviving records of Egypt’s laws, though we know that they were also written down.  On this question, however, we have the witness of Diodorus Siculus, who wrote in the 1st c. BC.  He noted that the Greeks derived several of their laws from the Egyptians, and the following quotation may give us reasoning behind the stated law from both:

Pregnant women [in Egypt] who had been condemned to death were not executed until they had been delivered. The same law has also been enacted by many Greek states, since they held it entirely unjust that the innocent should suffer the same punishment as the guilty, that a penalty should be exacted of two for only one transgression, and, further, that, since the crime had been actuated by an evil intention, a being as yet without intelligence should receive the same correction, and, what is the most important consideration, that in view of the fact that the guilt had been laid at the door of the pregnant mother it was by no means proper that the child, who belongs to the father as well as to the mother, should be despatched; for a man may properly consider judges who spare the life of à murderer to be no worse than other judges who destroy that which is guilty of no crime whatsoever (Diodorus Siculus, Library of History I.77.9-10).[1]

A pregnant woman condemned to death for a crime would not be executed until she delivered her child.  The reasoning might be restated in separate points:

1.     The unborn child was his/her own person, a separate person from his/her mother;

2.     The unborn child lacks responsibility for the crime of his/her mother and should not be punished along with the mother for the act—he/she is not guilty of the crime;

3.     The unborn child lacks intelligence and therefore cannot be punished along with the mother for intent;

4.     The unborn child belongs to both the mother and the father, not just the mother, and therefore any consideration of parental responsibility that ties the child to a parent (including guilt) is not the mother’s alone but is equally the father’s.

The reasoning given may have certain assumptions about human identity and rights, but this is not the focus.  Rather, legal questions regarding one’s own person, acts, intentions, and parental oversight are considered.  We might contrast Roman law to highlight the point that parental responsibility could be considered quite differently in antiquity.  Roman law placed the father in complete control over his household, and he had the power of life and death over his children:

But the lawgiver of the Romans gave virtually full power to the father over his son, even during his whole life, whether he thought proper to imprison him, to scourge him, to put him in chains and keep him at work in the fields, or to put him to death, and this even though the son were already engaged in public affairs, though he were numbered among the highest magistrates, and though he were celebrated for his zeal for the commonwealth (Dionysius of Hallicarnassus, The Roman Antiquities I.26.4).[2]

The master's authority over a slave in the Roman Empire was the same.  If a master chose to put a slave to death, he could.  Roman law treated the slave as property rather than as an enslaved human being (as in Egypt, Israel, and the rest of the Ancient Near East).  We can lay the notion that some humans are not legally protected as humans, are 'things', at the feet of ancient Roman culture and law.

The thinking of many in the West today about the status of the foetus and about abortion rights develops along the Roman lines, rejects an important assumption of the Egyptians and Greeks, and introduces an entirely new concept.  The Roman notion of parental responsibility and slavery that transferred all responsibility and authority to the father or master and therefore did not protect the child, born or unborn, under the law is still in view in the modern version of this line of thinking.

There are three differences, however.  First, the present argument has to do with an unborn child and, for some, the child right up to or at the time of birth.  Second, the present argument reverses the Roman thinking in that the mother, not the father, is given all the authority over the child’s life.  This is because, third, the Egyptian and Greek thinking that the child is a separate person is rejected.  Thus, the argument is often heard that ‘a woman can do what she wants with her body.’  This treats the unborn child as a body part of the woman that can be removed like a wart or, perhaps more specifically, like a life-depleting organism that can be removed.  The Egyptians and Greeks thought more in terms of parental, not just paternal (or now maternal) authority and responsibility, and they also insisted that the unborn child was a separate person.

Those pressing for abortion in the West today are beholden to a worldview that:

1.     Rejects the separate personhood of the foetus that Egyptians and Greeks accepted;

2.     Turns lack of intent on the part of a developing foetus from being a matter of innocence to being proof of dependency  and therefore a matter of not having rights;

3.     Transfers parental responsibility from the father (Roman) to the mother in the case of the unborn and, more importantly,

4.     Treats the unborn as non-human, not to be protected by the law, and an organic mass that a woman might remove if she chooses.

Remarkably, this contemporary argument has been cast as moral through its association with ‘human rights’ in the European, Enlightenment tradition and ‘women’s rights’ in the contemporary, Western tradition.  Western authorities, and those like the World Health Organisation that are beholden to this reasoning, try to force other cultures with their own and older moral traditions to comply with their ethic.  The promotion of abortion through such organisations is cultural imperialism at best and a recent innovation in moral reasoning that justifies the death of the unborn child. 

To be sure, ancient cultures practiced abortion, and the Greeks and Romans practiced infanticide. Something more was needed to protect the life of an unborn child. The Jewish-Christian tradition added the moral justification that humans were not to be put to death because they were different from animals in this regard: they were created in the image of God:

Whoever sheds the blood of a human, by a human shall that person’s blood be shed; for in his own image God made humankind (Genesis 9.6, ESV).

Not only is the unborn child a separate person, innocent of criminal acts, without evil intent, and the charge of both mother and father; the unborn child is also created in the image of God.  Christian tradition has also emphasised and developed morally along the Jewish-Christian trajectory of protecting the vulnerable. The Modernist focus on science moved the moral question of abortion from protection of the vulnerable, including the foetus, to whether a life was viable.[3] 

The West, or a very vocal and representative faction in the West, has been trying to unwind its own moral development over many centuries for the past several decades, particularly in regard to the protection of the life of the unborn,  It has instead not only developed but also is trying to enforce its new moral arguments for abortion on the rest of the world, tying this to foreign aid or promoting it through ‘health’, education, and women’s rights.[4] 

In a postmodern world of moral relativism, it inconsistently champions its moral reasoning as universal, a human ‘right’ to choose life or death for the unborn.  In a post-paternalistic society, it has advocated the rights of the woman over the man, especially in regard to abortion.  In a post-Enlightenment world, it advocates scientific grounds for morality on the basis of viability rather than a Judeo-Christian concern to aid the vulnerable.  While losing its own scientific arguments as the early development of the foetus has been demonstrated more and more, it nevertheless insists on abortion as a right (since the scientific argument was all along really only a foil).  In a post-Christian world, arguments about the human person as precious and protected for its being created in the image of God are rejected in favour of ‘my rights’ and ‘women’s rights’.



[1] Diodorus, Diodorus of Sicily in Twelve Volumes, Books I-II, trans. C. H. Oldfather (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 1933).

[2] Dionysius of HalicarnassusRoman Antiquities, Volume I: Books 1-2, trans. Earnest Cary (Loeb Classical Library 319; Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1937).

[3] See further, Rollin G. Grams, ‘Abortion, Culture, and the Church: Moving from Questions of Viability to Concerns for Vulnerability,’ Bible and Mission (May 5, 2017); online at: https://bibleandmission.blogspot.com/2017/05/abortion-culture-and-church-moving-from.html (accessed 3 October, 2023).

[4] This essay is not meant to be read as anti-Western but to explain the West’s role in cultural imperialism in regard to abortion.  China is hardly any improvement over the West in this regard.


No comments:

Return to Eden

 [A short story.] ‘Eve!   Wow!   Wonderful to see you after so long!   My badness, look at you!   How the hell did you get back in here?’   ...

Popular Posts